Skip to main content

Exciting Life Updates

I know I haven’t been updating this blog because I’m too lazy. Years 2 and 3 have been an exciting flurry of business (both work and busy-ness). I constantly spew bite-sized thoughts that stream into my mind on Instagram Stories anyway, and I am remarkably easily bored and excitable, so longer, more considered pieces on Blogger aren’t sustainable. I digress. Many exciting life updates! I’m now officially done with my undergraduate PPE programme at King’s College London. I loved every bit of it: the depth, rigour and intellectual intensity of the course, the international student community, the bustling city of London and all the travel opportunities around Europe. Words can’t do justice to the profundity of the experience. In typical Quincean fashion, I milked everything I could out of the three years: went to Cumberland Lodge (for free) as a photographer with the Philosophy Department in Years 1 and 3, clinched the Principal’s Global Leadership Award (PGLA) in my second year (spending

Hume’s Is–Ought Gap and Ought-Implies-Can

David Hume is credited with formulating the is–ought gap (also known as Hume’s Law) in Treatise 3.1.1.27:

I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation, which may, perhaps, be found of some importance. In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remark'd, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs; when of a sudden I am surpriz'd to find, that instead of the usual copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, 'tis necessary that it shou'd be observ'd and explain'd; and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention wou'd subvert all the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceiv'd by reason.

This passage is often interpreted as Hume positing a complete bifurcation between the worlds of “is” and “ought”, fact and value, description and prescription. Critics have responded with examples that seem to bridge both worlds, such as promissory obligation (the fact that one has made a promise implies that one is obligated to fulfil that promise) and how modality circumscribes morality (the Ought Implies Can principle and its equivalent, Impossible Implies Omissible).

Ought Implies Can:

\begin{equation*} O \phi \vDash \Diamond \phi \end{equation*}

Impossible Implies Omissible:

\begin{equation*} \neg \Diamond \phi \vDash \neg O \phi \end{equation*}

Against these challenges, Russell (2021) has recently worked to prove Hume’s Law. But, as a mere incoming Year 2 undergraduate, her logical work is beyond me. Nonetheless, it appears to me that a more modest version of the is–ought gap can meet these challenges. After all, the is–ought gap is often invoked, especially by social progressives, to support the view that just because something is the case doesn’t mean it should be the case. This invocation is not an attack on all connections (if any) between fact and value, but on logical inferences of a specific kind, which I formulate as Modest Is–Ought Gap.

Modest Is–Ought Gap:

\begin{equation*} \phi \not \vDash O \phi \end{equation*}

There is no contradiction between Modest Is–Ought Gap and Ought Implies Can. Looking back at Treatise 3.1.1.27, Hume is evidently sceptical about logical leaps from “is” to “ought”, but he says nothing about modality: “can” or “must”. Indeed, facts and descriptions include not only “is” claims, but also “can” and “must” claims. Therefore, on this modest view, it is an oversimplification to say that Hume’s is–ought gap separates all fact from value, or all description from prescription. Hume’s is–ought gap, at its core, separates a particular type of fact from value, and a particular type of description from prescription.

That, I can raise a glass of Scotch to. Sláinte! 🥃 ∎

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

H2 Knowledge and Inquiry (KI): Should You Take It?

Choosing your A Level subject combination can be quite a nerve-racking experience, especially if you don't have any strong interest in particular subjects. The stakes are high too: it's the A Levels, the culmination of 12 years of formal education. No one wants to screw up and pick the wrong combination that will lead to 2 years of extra suffering. I faced the same problem after I graduated from the High School section. Physics, Math, Literature and KI was the combination of my dreams, but it wasn't a standard combination the College section offered. I made a compromise and chose the closest combination on the standard list: KI, Literature, Math and Economics (KILME). When I tell people I take KILME, they usually respond with confusion or shock. "Harh, simi combi is that?" "You take KI?!?!?!" These reactions are basically caused by the mystery that is KI. It's a phantom subject: one that has no textbook, no published notes,

Analysis of "This I Fear Most" by Ng Yi-Sheng

When I first found this gem of a poem in "A Book of Hims", I knew it would be my favourite for a long time. The poem is so sweet, it's ridiculous. If Ed Sheeran's "Perfect" was a sonnet, this would be it. This I Fear Most Ng Yi-Sheng That I am not a light to guide you home, No shining beacon and no candle flame. That I am but a ragged burden thrown Against the bony shoulders of your frame, And every path you tread into the night I do encumber. That I do mistake That sunny grin for spirit and delight, Though it is worn to better bear the ache. This I fear most. So I command you: should You tire of me, strip me from your back And burn me like a hecatomb of wood. With raging heat, the heavens I’ll attack Until the dark dissolves away like foam. Then step ahead. My light shall guide you home. Analysis "This I Fear Most" by Ng Yi-Sheng is a Shakespearean sonnet about the selfless nature of love and the re

Hume on Reason and the Passions — A Reply to Zizai

The Awkward Yeti on Facebook I thank  Cui Zizai  — my old friend, former classmate, collaborator and interlocutor — for this opportunity to revisit Hume. Zizai sent me an email (one of his periodic circulars on mathematics, politics and philosophy) regarding his take on Hume, in particular the infamous line “reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions” in Hume’s  A Treatise of Human Nature (“ Treatise ”). Sent 1:28 am, 26 December 2020 (UTC+08:00) Zizai has two concerns which I shall attempt to address: Is the bipartite claim “reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions” is–ought fallacious? Does Hume offer an argument for his “ought” claim? How can it be justified? Is the bipartite claim “reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions” is–ought fallacious? Let us refer to Hume’s introduction of the is–ought problem ( Treatise  3.1.1.27 ): I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation, which may, perhaps, be found of some importance.